RADHIKA'S CATS (1)
Radhika(2) has two extremely intelligent cats, Peri and Samir. Samir
is the A-cat, and is clearly dominant -- a behavior common not only
to mammals, and clearly instinct-driven. (Hierarchy ensures discipline and order, and is therefore an adaptive trait.) As A-cat,
however, Samir tends to monopolize the food supply, and his humans
were concerned that B-cat Peri was not getting his fair share of
the food they set out. The solution to this dilemma: put one of
the food bowls on top of the refrigerator -- a spot reachable by
Peri in a single bound, something that Samir could not achieve.
Samir, however, learned to jump first to the kitchen table,
and then to the refrigerator top. In their next counter-move, the
humans placed the kitchen door ajar, into a position blocking the
space between table and refrigerator. But Samir tackled this challenge as well: he learned to push the door closed with his paw (a
task requiring a fair amount of sustained effort), after which the
path from floor to table to refrigerator top was again clear. So
the humans then did what humans are good at: escalate. They
propped the door open with a door-stop. And Samir again rose to
the challenge: he worked at the door-stop until it fell away; then
worked at the door; and finally used the table to access
refrigerator top and food. Our amateur ethologists thus witnessed
a sustained sequence of actions, linking cause to effect repeatedly
in pursuit of a goal. The proximate moral of the story: never
underestimate the intelligence and creativity of animals.
The episode's deeper message, of course, is to question the
claim, defended by this writer in "'Twixt Creationism and
Reductionism," Editorial Perspectives, Winter 1997-98, that human
consciousness and action have a distinctive quality not shared with
other living species. This quality has been termed "symbolic
reactivity," "symboling," and (more recently) "symbolic reference"
(Terrence W. Deacon, The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of
Language and the Brain, Norton, 1997). The idea that human
symbolic and cultural functioning creates a crucial watershed,
effectively transcending and (in a sense to be carefully stated)
replacing biological determination of behavior and biological
evolution, was also challenged in a thoughtful response by Janet
McIntosh ("Symbolism, Cognition, and Political Orders," Winter
1998-99).
After due consideration -- and with apologiees for the long
silence -- I would like to defend the claim, and explore its
properties a bit further. I regard the distinction itself as the
central issue; human uniqueness in its possession is a distinctly
secondary matter. But this is all the more reason to examine
Samir's behavior with care, to see if human consciousness
(including problem-solving ability) is indeed unique, in a way that
has implications for directionality in social evolution and
prospects for advancement toward, in McIntosh's words, "more
egalitarian and progressive social orders."
At issue are the pathways that build upon the simplest form of
an organism's interaction with its environment -- the unconditioned
reflex, or built-in (instinct-driven) response to a stimulus (in
the case of Samir, the striving for food). The unconditioned
reflex is genetically encoded, and therefore the result of natural
selection of an adaptive behavior, a selection that takes place in
biological time. Behavior and survival-chances are enriched, as is
well known, by the elaboration of this mechanism into the
conditioned reflex: new behaviors not present in the genome can be
created, and other behaviors extinguished, by associating an
intrinsic stimulus with an external one. The external stimulus is
arbitrary, as in the well-known behaviorist experiments inducing
responses in animals to light or sound events, by associating these
events with intrinsically pleasurable or painful stimuli (food;
electric shock). The secondary stimulus is arbitrary, but the
association must be imposed on the organism from outside.
In the next stage of this evolution, the last two properties
are reversed: the organism itself makes the association, but
between stimuli that are inherently connected in the environment.
This is learning. Unlike the conditioned reflex, which can be
observed or induced in many animal orders, learning appears to
emerge only in mammals.(3) It involves the (usually sudden)
occurrence of insight: the moment at which a connection is
established, between a simple tool and an outcome (chimpanzees
inserting a stick into an anthill), or between a table and a
refrigerator top. Learning greatly improves organismic reactivity:
the organism makes the connection directly, rather than waiting for
natural occurrences (or laboratory researchers) to impose it. With
the underlying hunger (and, perhaps, dominance) drive in place,
Samir learns one connection (table--refrigerator top); builds that
connection into a conditioned response; then learns a new
connection (move door--table) and builds the new connection into
the conditioned chain; and finally learns a third connection (move
doorstop--door), adding that one to the chain. In the absence of
symbols -- the exhaustive grid of meanings that enables the
organism to do all this abstractly, independently of the sensory
field, and prior to acting -- this is an impressive intellectual
achievement.(4)
Symbolic reference completes the sequence. Symbols are
arbitrary elements (constructed out of signs, largely but not
exclu-sively linguistic) associated with objects or elements of
experience by the organisms themselves. Here a shift in point of
reference occurs: symbols emerge as elements of communication among
individuals, and have an inherently relational quality. But with
that understanding, they represent an alternative framework of
meaning -- a set of abstractions -- that intervenes between
external stimuli and behavior. Symbol processing thus precedes
action; moreover, action takes place -- and can only take place --
on the basis of symbolic representations. "External" in this
formulation refers to elements in the objective environment outside
the organism (and cooperating organisms), but also, and crucially,
to impulses coming from the genetic "interior." The inclusiveness
and exhaustiveness of the symbolic field assures that no behavior
of the organism, other than the most elementary reflexes and the
functions of the autonomic nervous system, can result from an
automatic triggering source. This "freeing of [from] instinct" is
the central reproductive strategy along the chain of evolution
leading through the primates to homo sapiens. We are driven by,
e.g., hunger, or sexual desire, but we cannot avoid translating
these feelings into the superorganic realm of symbols before we act
on them. We cannot grasp them purely emotionally, or in terms of
picture-thinking; the symbolic reference field cannot be turned
off.
The following schematic may help in nailing down the stages in
the development of organismic reactivity, or reference. (This is
my own construction, but it is based on Becker's
conceptualization.)
|
|
Connection between stimuli |
|
|
Intrinsic |
Arbitrary |
Response of organism |
Other-initiated |
Unconditioned Reflex |
Conditioned Reflex |
Self-initiated |
Learning |
Symbolic Reference |
What presumably distinguishes the dullest of human beings from the
brightest of cats (Samir) is the distinction, often missed in
casual discussions, between learning and symbolic reference along
the bottom row of this table.(5)
Deacon (work cited, ch. 3) develops a different conceptual
hierarchy, in which the transitions are from iconic reference, to
indexical reference, and finally to symbolic reference. Refer to
this work for massive amounts of information about both human and
animal behavior, and the crucial concept of co-evolution. The
upshot is the defining insight that comes down to us in many forms,
from Adam eating the fruit of the Tree of Knowledge in Genesis, to
Marx's 1844 elaborations on human species being. This is the
cultural universal -- the missing link between biological
universals and the cultural particularities so beloved of the "new
creationists" targeted by Barbara Ehrenreich and Janet McIntosh.
The universe of symbols imposes the ability (and need): to posit
and manipulate contrary-to-fact situations; to be aware of space
and time and their negations, i.e., to know of non-existence and
death; to possess the acute self-consciousness that we call the
Self, or the Ego, a symbolic abstraction that thus has language and
culture as an unavoidable premise(6); to elaborate frameworks of
meaning, cosmology, ideology; and much else.
McIntosh finds my assertion that "culture . . . has
effectively replaced nature, insofar as behavior and consciousness
are concerned" too sweeping. I am inclined to agree, and now
prefer a revised formulation: the natural influences on
consciousness and behavior can only take place symbolically, and
therefore culturally (in the sense of the cultural universal).
McIntosh wants to argue against what she calls the "sponge theory"
of consciousness -- that the human mind simply absorbs (soaks up)
anything that culture imposes on it. The transcendent-culture view
that I am defending should be clearly distinguishable from any
version of what we used to call Watsonian behaviorism, a position
staked out at the "nurture" end of the "nature-nurture" spectrum.
Like McIntosh, I believe that the spectrum itself should be
transcended. She refers to studies that "suggest" the existence of
certain universal psychological characteristics, such as a tendency
(observed even in small children) to posit the existence of
"insides" and "outsides" in other sentient beings (a form of
"essentialism"), and a tendency to posit the existence of "unseen
contaminative forces," presumably common to all or many cultures.
These may be called "innate cognitive predispositions," as McIntosh
does, but much turns on the interpretation of "innate."
Essentialism is clearly impossible without symbols, as is the
positing of unseen forces, contaminative or otherwise.
Essentialism, in turn, is thought to be a basis for extra-group
hostility, prejudice, etc.; McIntosh is concerned to extract the
implications of innate predispositions for the existence and
exercise of power in social life. This is a complex subject; I
will simply note here that even if we assume that there is an
innate tendency for all human beings to produce essentialist
(inner/outer) conceptions, there is no reason to link this to an
inherent trope toward "racial or gendered thinking": witness the
counter-claim of universal human goodness and worth, an essence
posited by some religious philosophies, which would work against
multiple "essences" that divide. The "innate" turns out once again
to be symbolic, and to be "recruitable" for a full spectrum of
ideologies buttressing different systems of definition and power,
including ones that transcend domination and exploitation.
I must reiterate the claim that we -- humans -- are not now
evolving biologically. McIntosh writes that "in some communities"
the role of natural selection has withered. I am not aware,
however, of any communities in which cultural practices have not
radically separated reproductive success from genetically inherited
characteristics. Some private communications received from
biologists have referred to changes in the gene pool brought about
by the humanly transformed environment -- e.g., the effect of the
huge increase in sugar consumption in the last century, or in the
presence of industrial pollutants. These could induce a form of
"Baldwinian evolution" (Deacon, ch. 11), in which environmental
changes brought about by human beings serve as the framework for
adaptive genetic innovations -- except for the fact that massive
medical, technological and cultural intervention prevent these
adaptations from becoming effective. The matter cannot be resolved
by general pronouncements, such as: ". . . human phylogenesis has
left its mark on the human genome" (McIntosh). I hope my
correspondents will write for publication on this topic.
Finally, the question must have occurred to many readers: how
do we (claim to) know any of this? And: why does it matter? On
the first, I have no simple answer, except to say that profound
truths about the human condition are neither innate, nor simply
empirical! On the second: if we can (legitimately) secure the
understanding that human consciousness and action are qualitatively
and irreversibly symbolic, the surest foundation is laid for the
most central claim of historical materialism: the conditional
inevitability (see "Editorial Perspectives," Spring 2000) of
progress toward a society of equality, solidarity and fulfillment.
This is the (conditional) directionality of history: progress is
inevitable -- because it is possible. We have also the insight
that an intentional society is the fullest embodiment of symbolic
reference; that social evolution consists essentially of growth in
the ability of human beings to bring their own development under
deliberative, and in that sense symbolic, control (see our special
issue, "Building Socialism Theoretically," Spring 2002).
___________________
1. Not to be confused with the T. S. Eliot Practical variety, or
with Schroedinger's (possibly unfortunate; we'll never know)
Cat, or with the late unlamented Broadway musical.
2. Radhika Lal, a colleague living in New York, development
economist, and housemate of our senior editor, Dr. Annette T.
Rubinstein, to whom I am indebted for this story.
3. An important source for this discussion is Ernest Becker, The
Birth and Death of Meaning. Becker draws heavily on Leslie
White, The Science of Culture, and I share that influence. I
should perhaps mention that I find White's attempted theory of
cultural evolution to be less useful than his perceptive
discussion of symbols and their implications, in the early
chapters of the work cited.
4. In African Genesis, Robert Ardrey -- in total contradiction to
his reductionist intentions! -- provides a magnificent
illustration of the distinction between symbolic and non-symbolic reference. South African farmers, plagued by crop-stealing baboons, move into the planted fields and hide, while
the baboons watch from the safety of the surrounding jungle.
One farmer hides in the field, while the rest retreat. The
baboons will return to the field (to their peril), if they are
fooled into thinking that all of the farmers are gone; this
rests on their ability to count. Experience revealed that the
baboons could count up to four or five, but got confused
trying to distinguish quantities above those numbers. Imagine
trying to "count" items by sheer perception, burdened with the
necessity of receiving all of the rich extraneous particulars
in the sensory field, i.e., without numbers (symbols). A
daunting task. By contrast, with symbols, they could, in
principle, distinguish between 1,000,000 farmers and 999,999.
Numbers clearly illustrate the exhaustive quality of symbols:
n implies n + 1. There is no quantity for which there is not
a number.
5. The conceptual lacuna is illustrated in recent reporting on
research by Frans B. M. de Waal at the Yerkes Regional Primate
Research Center in Atlanta, Georgia. The findings consist of
observations of behavioral variations among different
communities of chimpanzees, as summarized in de Waal's most
recent book, The Ape and the Sushi Master: Cultural
Reflections by a Primatologist (Basic Books, 2001).
Summarizing work reported in the journal Nature in 1999, a
reporter writes: "The researchers came up with 39 behavior
patterns that fit their definition of cultural variation,
meaning they were customary in some communities and absent in
others, for reasons that could only be explained by learning
or imitation" (New York Times, June 17, 1999). De Waal, in a
commentary on this report, finds the evidence "so impressive
that it will be hard to keep these apes out of the cultural
domain without once again moving the goal posts." I can
assure him a) that, on my part at least, the goal posts will
move no further than the distinction between learning and
symbolic reference, a distinction that does not seem to have
occurred to most members of the primatological community; and
b) that -- as indicated above -- should symbolic reference
indeed be found to exist among primates the "uniqueness" of
human beings can readily be abandoned, so long as the
qualitative singularity and dynamic inclusiveness of symbols
as such are grasped.
6. Recall Marx's prescient anticipation of symbolic
interactionist social psychology: "In a sort of way, it is
with man as with commodities. Since he comes into the world
neither with a looking glass in his hand, nor as a Fichtian
philosopher, to whom 'I am I' is sufficient, man first sees
and recognizes himself in other men. Peter only establishes
his own identity as a man by first comparing himself with Paul
as being of like kind. And thereby Paul, just as he stands in
his Pauline personality, becomes to Peter the type of the
genus homo" (Capital, I, ch. 1, sec. 3).
Continue to next Page